Is Historical Injustice A Justification For Taxation?

Libertarians tent to think that taxation is theft. Taking someone’s private property by force can hardly be called anything else, right? And yet, most people seem to find this argument rather unconvincing. Many probably have never thought about this issue very deeply and just accept taxation as normal and unavoidable and therefore legitimate.

But there are people who have thought about it and have tried to answer the libertarian theft claim. One popular argument they have come up with is that it is the state that enables the existence of private property. Without the state we would not have it. From this point of view, it is then easy to argue that the state does not really steal anything through taxes but merely withholds its own property, the property of society, instead. This argument however is little convincing. There are too many examples of non state societies that had some concept of property. In fact, I am not aware that there have ever been societies that did not know any type of private property.

Because this argument seems easily debunked, the advocates of taxation are increasingly moving towards a more subtle argument. Yes, they concede, there are very legitimate forms of property. If someone produces something with his own labour, it is hard to argue that this should not be his to keep. However, they also argue that there is one type of private property which seems difficult to justify and makes all other private property questionable. The property in question is private land ownership.

Land exists independent of human beings. With what right does someone claim sole usage of such a scarce resource? There have been, and still are, plenty of societies to whom the concept of individual land ownership is alien. Land clearly has to belong to everyone equally.

The most common libertarian answer to this objection comes from the philosopher David Hume. Hume argued that land can be legitimately, privately owned, if someone mixes his labour with it. He called this concept homesteading. Some of the extra value of this homesteaded land is now due to a person’s labour. So not letting him own that land means to free-load on that labour and therefore exploit him.

This is not a bad argument. However, I never found it entirely convincing either. It looks a bit like a fudge. It seems, the argument is used to somehow, almost forcefully, justify land ownership, a conclusion that really stands before the argument. In other words, land ownership does not seem to follow from the cheer force of the argument.

There are multiple convincing ways to attack homesteading. Firstly, one could argue, fine, the homesteader can keep the extra value he has created. But every land still has some value beyond this added labour value. For example, an import part of the value of land is location, location, location. It clearly matters, whether I build a house in the middle of flyover land or in the middle of Manhattan. Why would I alone be able to keep the full value? If the location is valuable to a lot of people, and I have not created that value, would it not be correct to argue that I still owe the others some compensation for my sole usage? This could be a good argument for taxation of land.

Another extra value the landowner might get is natural resources. I own some land because I have mixed my labour with it. Beneath that land is a lot of oil. Do I now have the sole right to exploit that oil, even though I did not create any of it? Again, would it not be at least fair to tax someone for the exploitation of natural resources?

The most obvious flaw with the homesteading argument however is that this is not how most land got into private ownership. Historically, the most common form of acquiring land was through conquest. Some government just took it and distributed it among its followers. In England for example, there is still a lot of land which is owned by royals. Most of the other land in private ownership was at some point acquired from royals. There is not much homesteading by the owners here, just a violent take over. Clearly that cannot be right. As a result, an increasingly popular argument for taxation in general is to say that, even though there might be a legitimate form of property, this does not apply to a lot of property today. Ownership of land and resources was historically almost universally acquired in not legitimate ways. Therefore, current property owners owe society compensation for the usage of this illegitimately acquired property.

Why the historical injustice argument does not work

This is not a bad argument and it deserves a detailed answer. In my view there are several flaws in it. The first is that it is automatically assumed that there is such an object like ‘society’ with a common will and interests. The existence of such a society seems necessary in order to argue for taxation on the basis of historical injustice. But such a society does not exist. Instead taxes are being paid to the state. The state however is a very different beast. It cannot solve the problem of scarcity, which is at the heart of this problem. Instead, the state runs into the exact same problem as the land owner.

Let us assume we could figure out exactly how much of the Manhattan house value is due to labour and how much to location. Of course, such an assessment is impossible. Valuations are inherently subjective and too many factors need to be considered. But for the sake of the argument let us assume we could obtain objective information. The taxes the house owner pays as compensation for the location would not go to benefit every other person on the planet. Instead the money is distributed towards specific groups of people.

So the question arrises, why do only these groups of people get that money and not everyone else? If we do give it to a group of people and not everyone equally, then the argument does not resolve the special interest at the centre of the problem. Instead of the Manhattan house owner getting the full benefit, we just have decided to use a different mechanism to distribute this special interest. But it is not clear why this is supposed to be more just. And even if it were just equally just, is it really a better, as in easier, solution to be preferred to private property? Given that we cannot even figure out how much of the value is exactly due to his labour, this solution looks in fact more arbitrary and vulnerable to abuse. In no way is this a justification for allowing a government to raise taxes and distribute them as it see fit. The idea that taxes benefit a society as a whole is simply factually false. Whenever people talk about society, they are trying to disguise special interests.

Still, the libertarian claim that taxation is always theft assumes legitimate property. And libertarians do not argue that property which is acquired by conquest is legitimate. Yet that is how most land ownership was acquired historically. Is property really legitimate when it stands in a tradition of illegitimate property claims? It looks to me like the answer is, it depends. But homesteading is probably not a good, or at least not a sufficient argument for land ownership today. We have to come up with something better.

Libertarians argue for a maximum of individual liberty. That means they argue that everyone should be left alone, by other people, to live their lives as they please. That is not to say that libertarians argue in favour of everyone being a lone wolf. Of course, everyone is free to interact with other people if that is what they choose to do with their lives. But ideally no one should proactively interfere with other people’s projects in life.

Since we live in a scarce world, absolute individual liberty unfortunately seems impossible. Sometimes we will have to involuntarily get into each other’s hair. But libertarians try to come up with rules that keep these involuntary interactions at a minimum. Private property is an example of such a rule. We need to respect certain types of ownership for it to become possible to leave people alone in a scarce world.

A scarce, desirable resource, by its nature, cannot be used by everyone. For example, if I burn this litre of petrol in my car, you cannot also burn it in yours. And we certainly cannot burn it for society as a whole. That means that collective ownership, as advocated by a lot of socialists, does not solve this problem. Nature forces us to come up with some form of special usage rights for desirable scarce resources.

I would argue that if we want to maximise liberty, that means if we want to minimise involuntary interferences of people with each other’s life projects, private property on these scarce resources looks like the best solution. Why is that?

Well, what would be the alternative? It seems the only alternative is either some form of collective ownership, or no ownership and the right of the strongest, or a rule that no one uses the recourse at all. I am not going to spend much time arguing why the last two solutions are bad, as that seems pretty obvious. In both cases, people would have massive interferences with their projects in life, either by not being able to use resources at all, or by constantly having to fear for the future of their projects.

But collective ownership also seems like a worse solution to private property. As we have seen above, collective ownership cannot mean that everyone enjoys the benefits of a resource or product equally. It is merely a different way of deciding, which individuals can use it. This could come in various forms. It could be decided democratically, in which case the minority never gets to engage in their projects in life. It could be by throwing a dice and let luck decide, in which case only the lucky get to engage in their favourite projects. Or it could be a rotation system, in which case everyone can occasionally realise their favourite project, but most of the time, we would be condemned to help others fulfilling theirs.

Private property seems superior to all of these solutions to maximise liberty. With private property, everyone can do what they like with their belongings. That way they can just pursue their projects as they like with at least some resources. That, on its own, makes it the clear liberty maximising solution out of all the other known solutions.

But there are extra benefits. The beauty of this solution is that no one is stuck with the property they already have. If you require a resource that is important to a project of yours, you can make the current owner an offer for that resource. The more important the project is for you, the more you are likely to bit for the resource you need. And the more you bit, the more likely you are to obtain ownership of it.

That way, markets have a tendency to get resources into the hands of people that have the most use for them. Consequently, these resources get used most effectively. In addition to that, private property also offers incentives to come up with solutions to make desirable resources and products less scarce. As a result, a side effect of private property is that it actually reduces the scarcity, which is at the centre of why we have this problem in the first place. No other solution has this extra benefit. It is these extra benefits which even make people support the libertarian solution who are not primarily interested in liberty.

What does this mean to our initial question, whether historical injustice justifies redistribution of wealth, or in other words taxation? It seems clear to me that if an individual can show a historic claim on a concrete property, then that needs to be respected.

Short of that however, what we want is that people have access to the resources they require for their important projects in life. Over time, free markets tend towards that solution. This is true independent of how resources came into private ownership. To put it differently, even if there is non libertarian property at the start, as in the example of royals owning land, over time, the right people are going to become the owners of the resources they need. Markets are great in solving problems, and they even solve the problem of illegitimate property over time.

The recent history of Zimbabwe is a good example of the relevance of this insight. It would be hard to argue that the white farm owners, who were owning most of the land in the country until not too long ago, acquired their farms with legitimate means. They indeed stole it from the locals. Because of the historical injustice, the Mugabe government started to randomly, meaning without any concrete individual historical claims, to redistribute these farms among their supporters. Did this make these new owners rich and happy? Not really. Few of them had any idea about farming. If they had had better farming skills than the white owners, they could have made the latter a very attractive offer to take over the farms on the market. But farming was not really any of their projects in life. The result is that the land changed ownership from people who had use for it to people who had no use for it. Zimbabwe went from being a big food exporter to starvation as a result. Everyone’s projects in life, except maybe for a small group of ruling class members, were disrupted.

Contrary to the myth, private property does not protect a class of wealthy people and their interests. It is a tool that serves everyone to pursue their interests in life. In the process, we can constantly see poor people becoming wealthy and wealthy people becoming poor. That means that property changes hands from people who cannot handle it to people who can. Even though, some people might go from wealthy to poor, overall everyone gets richer. Within this process, people actually have a very good chance of pursuing their most important projects in life. That means that private property on scarce, desired resources advances the cause of individual liberty better than any other known mechanism of distributing usage rights on these resources. It is unclear, what taxes have to add to all of this. They are no solution to the underlying problem of scarcity. In fact they make it worse.

Video: Sax and Violence : why does tax get a free ride?

This is the first Libertarian Home talk that I have felt compelled to prefix with a health warning. The libertarian movement has an unjustified reputation for being a) cold-hearted and uncaring b) predominantly male and occasionally c) juvenile. I recall Jack of Kent for example defining a libertarian as a liberal who has not left home yet (it is more likely the precise opposite, if you understand the importance of personal accountability in this school of thought).

For those not present, the speaker had written a fictional essay; explaining the serious matter of sexual inequality in the parallel world of Equistan. The problem was caused by men suddenly out numbering women four to one, and the democratic solution was that those lucky individuals found to be enjoying an active sex life were asked to share some of their sex life with people who were otherwise struggling to get laid on their own merits. All the justifications given for tax are applied to “sax”.

The subject matter and the sound of giggling men creates an obvious risk that this video simply justifies critics’ existing impressions of our community. I have by now listened to the video several times over, and was present when the original essay was read aloud to an exclusive audience in Pimlico. At first I cringed, for the above reasons, when hearing my colleagues giggle at the content, but as I listen again (to check the edit, then the render, then the YouTube re-encoding, then again for this write up) I was able to notice patterns. The giggling is rarely if ever noticed when the speaker mentions sexual acts. Rape is not being laughed at in this video. The humour you hear is directed at the familiar justifications given for the notion of “Saxation”. The role of laughter is to dismiss the unreal or uncomfortable, and the very real justifications of tax that the speaker repurposed as justifications for rape needed to be processed in this way. Their unreality needed to be confirmed by laughing together as a group. I think the alternative for the group was anger or despair that the logical arguments presented for saxation through the first 12 minutes are in fact very real arguments for the all-too-real and ugly institution of taxation, an institution that robs the labour of more people than the slave trade ever did.

At least, that’s my amateur psychological explanation, but if you are not convinced then simply listen out for the females in the group from 8 to 12 minutes in. Why would they be tittering away at something that disproportionately affects them? They aren’t, they are laughing at progressive ideas they would otherwise find disgusting.

The second part of the talk drills into the psychology of how people process the ideas of saxation, taxation, theft and rape.

Acts of Violation by Substance and Perpetrator
State Citizen
Person Saxation Rape
Property Taxation Theft

Gregg sets about building a case that the special status of taxation as a moral good in mainstream thinking is an oddity in need of explanation. When considering the table as a whole it is possible to argue that:

  • If theft is wrong why is tax okay? (the traditional libertarian argument)
  • If rape and theft are wrong why would sax be okay? (Equistan has decided it is)
  • If rape and sax are wrong aren’t theft and tax both also wrong?
  • If theft and rape are bad shouldn’t tax as well as sax be wrong?
UK UnCut Supporter

UK UnCut Supporter

All these permutations are different ways of asking: why does society regard the payment of tax to be morally obligatory? It is certain that it does, for the most part, do so. UK UnCut, Margaret Hodge and even the Conservative David Cameron have all conducted witch hunts against those who might be paying less than others, even when already paying everything they are asked for under the law. The payment of Tax is regarded as beyond good, as essential in fact, to be considered a decent human being.

However Gregg was able to identify commonalities between all the things in the table that appear to justify the case that all four are bad:

Conflict

Sax, Rape, Tax and Theft all involve an essential conflict of interest in which resistance may become violent. Submission is safer but in any event the preferences of all the parties are not met.

Loss of Autonomy

Sax, Rape, Tax and Theft all involve a loss of autonomy, which is a basic human striving. Since all four acts involve coercion someone’s plans are sacrificed and frustrated for the sake of the plans of others.

Unjustified superiority

Thieves, tax collectors and public and private sector rapists all act on an assumption, held by the person employing force, that his needs or his intellect are superior to those of the other party and should take precedence.

Dignity

Rapists, tax collectors, perpetrators of systemic rape and common thieves all treat other people as the means to an end. Gregg identifies this as simply undignified, but I think he would agree that it offensive both to the individual and also devalues all individuals in the culture.

Moral relativism

Gregg goes on to preemptively deal with some objections to his theory that sax, theft, tax and rape are all evil.

The argument from seriousness, that personal violations are more serious than property violations. This is dismissed as inconsistent with other examples of decisions people might generally make (for example, the decision to sell sex) and also dismissed on principle (since even minor violations of property are still considered theft).

The argument from feasibility, that it is simply easier to tax wealth than sex is dismissed by way of a comparison with the mugging of an old lady or a “muscular gent”. It is easier to mug the old lady but that makes it worse, not better.

The argument from necessity, that tax is really useful and good things can be done with it is not highly regarded by most libertarians who argue that liberty generates useful stuff better than tax-and-spend does. Gregg takes an interesting turn here and rejects this argument on a very different basis: that sometimes rights trump utility. In the case of saxation our intuition is that women’s right of self-ownership trumps the utility of sorting out horny men and that perhaps our intuition about tax being in the opposite category might be wrong.

The argument from incredulity, that it is basically a silly comparison. Tax is a decent traditional social institution and it is ridiculous to make comparisons between good-old tax, the systemic exploitation of women. This is where the talk gets really interesting for me.

Gregg basically accepts the notion (which is false in my view) that morality is subjective. He accepts the Is-Ought dichotomy. He does reject geography and tradition as valid sources of moral standards but accepts a generalised zeitgeist which evolves with debate over time to exclude as ridiculous certain things that were once held to be valid, such as a disapproval of homophobia. He assumes that the more developed West has better moral insight than, say, African society and dwells on Female Genital Mutilation as an example. FGM he argued, is very common in some places in Africa and all that is required is for a more clear-thinking western influence to explain patiently that cutting up clitorises is not okay. We are invited to believe that Africa is like a parallel universe which would vanish in a puff of logic if exposed to better, more scientific, ideas. Gregg suggests that we are living in a similar bubble of taxation supporting primitives who need only have the truth explained to them. The story about saxation is cast in the role of a useful tool to burst our moral bubble and bring reality crashing in. Except, it doesn’t, not on it’s own.

Give me more!

The saxation story is certainly funny. I don’t doubt that it will get people thinking and that people will recognise thier own arguments in the arguments for saxation. But on hearing the talk five or six times – I can’t help but hope for more. The quick tour of moral subjectivist arguments in the 23rd minute reminds me that cold hard reality is a viable source for moral standards and we ought to use it. Hoping that a story about saxation will bring reality crashing in is limited if all you mean to do is bring the reality about tax into play. If you wanted to assert the role of reality as a source of moral standards in all cases, then you are going to need a bigger story.